“What the Picture Tells Me Is Itself”: The Reflexivity of Knowledge between Brandom and Wittgenstein

  • Vojtěch Kolman Charles University in Prague, Czech Republic
Keywords: Language Game, Self-Consciousness, Reflexivity, Game Metaphor, Hegel

Abstract

Both Brandom and Wittgenstein base their concepts of experience on the game metaphor and the associated concept of rule. In fact, what Brandom seems to do is further refine Wittgenstein’s vocabulary by specifying the game as the game of giving and asking for reasons and rules as the rules of inference. By replacing the plurality of “games” with the one and only “game”, though, Brandom also lays the ground for a possible discord. This relates particularly to the cognitive significance of different forms of human experience, such as music or art in general, which are treated by Wittgenstein as language games despite their being rather independent of claims and commitments and despite their utterly lacking the representational dimension. In my paper, I will show that with respect to these objections (as phrased, e.g., by Andrew Bowie), one can argue that Brandom is in fact true to Wittgenstein’s instruction to always read his Investigations against his Tractatus. The general idea is to look at the game and picture metaphor as parts of a single concept that both philosophers work on together by going back to the very idealist concept of reflexivity or self-consciousness.

Author Biography

Vojtěch Kolman, Charles University in Prague, Czech Republic

Vojtěch Kolman is Associate Professor of Logic at the Faculty of Arts, Charles University in Prague, Czech Republic. His research focuses mainly on themes from the philosophy of mathematics, the history of logic, pragmatism, and the philosophy of the arts. He is author of the book Zahlen (de Gruyter, 2016) and numerous articles in international journals (SyntheseErkenntnisHegel-BulletinAllgemeine Zeitschrift für Philosophie and others). He coedited From Rules to Meanings, New Essays in Inferentialism (Routledge, 2018).

References

Ball, Philip (2010). The Music Instinct, How Music Works and Why We Can‘t do Without It. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Brandom, Robert (1994). Making It Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Commitment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Brandom, Robert (1999). “Some Pragmatist Themes in Hegel’s Idealism: Negotiation and Administration in Hegel’s Account of the Structure and Content of Conceptual Norms”. European Journal of Philosophy 7:2, pp. 164–189. Doi: https://doi.org/10.1111/1468-0378.00079

Brandom, Robert (2000). Articulating Reasons. An Introduction to Inferentialism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Brandom, Robert (2007). “The structure of desire and recognition: self-consciousness and self-constitution”, Philosophy & Social Criticism 33:1, pp. 12 –150. Doi: https://doi.org/10.1177/0191453707071389

Brandom, Robert (2011). Perspectives on Pragmatism. Classical, Recent and Contemporary. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Brandom, Robert (Unpublished). A Spirit of Trust: A Semantic Reading of Hegel’s Phenomenology, unpublished manuscripts http://www.pitt.edu/~brandom/spirit_of_trust.html, version 2014.

Gettier, Edmund (1963). “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?”, Analysis 23:6, pp. 121–3. Doi: https://doi.org/10.1093/analys/23.6.121.

Harries, Karsten. (2001). Infinity and Perspective. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. Doi: https://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/3755.001.0001

Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich (1977). The Difference Between Fichte’s and Schelling’s System of Philosophy. Trans. by H. S. Harris and Walter Cerf. New York: State University of New York Press

Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. (2018). The Phenomenology of Spirit. Trans. by T. Pinkard. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Kolman, Vojtěch (2014a). “Normative Pragmatism and the Language Game of Music”, Contemporary Pragmatism 11:2, pp. 147–163. Doi: https://doi.org/10.1163/18758185-90000295

Kolman, Vojtěch (2014b). “Emotions and Understanding in Music: A Transcendental and Empirical Approach”, Idealistic Studies 44:1, pp. 83–100. Doi: https://doi.org/10.5840/idstudies20152317

Kolman, Vojtěch (2016). “Hegel’s Bad Infinity as a Logical Problem”, Hegel–Bulletin 37:2 pp. 257–280. Doi: https://doi.org/10.1017/hgl.2016.18

Kolman, Vojtěch (forthcoming). “Master, Slave, and Wittgenstein. The Dialectic of Rule–Following.” In: Wittgenstein and Hegel. Reevaluation of Difference, ed. by J. Mácha, A. Berg. Berlin: De Gryuter.

Kvasz, Ladislav (2008). Patterns of Change. Linguistic Innovations in the Development of Classical Mathematics. Basel: Birhäuser.

Massey, Lyle (2007). Picturing Space, Displacing Bodies. Anamorphosis in Early Modern Theories of Perspective. University Park, PA: The Pennsylvania State University Press.

Meyer, Leonard (1956). Emotion and Meaning in Music. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Price, Huw (2011). Naturalism Without Mirrors. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Scruton, Roger (1998). The Aesthetic Understanding. Essays in the Philosophy of Art and Culture. South Bend: St. Augustine‘s Press.

Sellars, Wilfrid (1997). Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1953). Philosophical Investigations. Oxford: Blackwell.

Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1958). The Blue and Brown Books. Oxford: Blackwell.

Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1961). Tractatus Logico–Philosophicus. Trans. by D. F. Pears and B. F. McGuinness. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1974). Philosophical Grammar. Trans. by Anthony Kenny. Oxford: Blackwell.

Published
2019-06-30
How to Cite
[1]
Kolman, V. 2019. “What the Picture Tells Me Is Itself”: The Reflexivity of Knowledge between Brandom and Wittgenstein. Disputatio. 8, 9 (Jun. 2019), 409-429. DOI:https://doi.org/10.5281/zenodo.3236883.